Jersey &
Guernsey Law Review – October 2013
The United Kingdom’s General Anti-Abuse Rule
in Tax
Dennis Dixon
The UK parliament has recently enacted a General
Anti-Abuse Rule (“UK
GAAR”) to counter egregious tax avoidance. This article considers the
impact of the UK GAAR on the
frequent controversy arising from so-called Jersey
Schemes. The conclusion is that the UK parliament will have delivered a
conclusive moral judgment as to what is immoral avoidance, and such schemes will
fail. In future, any Jersey institution involved in UK tax planning can be assured that
there is no moral risk, as egregious schemes are doomed to fail. The question
of whether Jersey ought to reform its own General Anti-Avoidance Rule to learn
from the UK’s
example will be considered. It will be argued that following the approach taken
by the UK GAAR would narrow
the focus and effectiveness of the current Jersey
provision, and add considerable bureaucracy.
1 This article concerns the United Kingdom’s
soon to be introduced General Anti-Abuse Rule (“UK GAAR”) against
“egregious” tax avoidance. The aim is to consider two questions. First,
whether the introduction of the GAAR has any consequences for Jersey
in terms of its association in the public mind with tax avoidance, which
frequently sees schemes designed by Britons for Britons styled as Jersey Schemes
whenever the matter reaches the popular press. Secondly, whether there are any
lessons which Jersey should take from the UK’s new legislation as regards
is own General Anti-Avoidance Rule (“Jersey GAAR”) found in s 134A
of the Income Tax (Jersey) Law.
2 What we shall see is that the UK parliament,
assuming that it passes the UK GAAR in its current form, chose to follow the
minimalistic view of what a general anti-avoidance rule should achieve proposed
by the Aaronson Report, more properly called the GAAR Study. More importantly from the
Jersey perspective, the UK GAAR follows Graham Aaronson, QC
in taking an approach which is one of moral objection but which also places
most avoidance in the unobjectionable middle ground. It was recently asked in
the States Assembly what “aggressive tax avoidance” is, and what Jersey is doing to fight it. At least as regards UK taxation, the UK GAAR provides both the answer
to the question of definition, and also tells Jersey
what it needs to do against such avoidance. In future, it will in most contexts
be impossible for Jersey to be involved in avoidance that the UK finds objectionable, for such
avoidance will by definition fail. However, as regards the question of what Jersey can learn from the UK GAAR in terms of dealing
with avoidance of its own direct taxes, the answer must be very little, if
anything. The UK GAAR takes a moralized view of avoidance, and thus does not
seek to achieve what all tax legislation should aim at: the accurate
measurement of income and expenditure—or at the very least the creation
of a realistic threat of achieving that aim in order to deter taxpayers from
trying to exploit possible shortcomings in the legislation. When enacted, the
UK GAAR will provide the UK
parliament’s moral blessing for
much of what might popularly be called tax avoidance as being in “the centre ground of responsible tax planning”. It does not follow that
this means that such planning works as a matter of law, just that any
accusation of immorality is removed.
The UK
GAAR
The history of thought
3 It is useful to set out the immediate
history of the UK GAAR, and in doing so to set out the legal backdrop to the
tax avoidance debate in the UK. All history, as
Collingwood put it, is the history of thought. This means that behind
everything that happens in human affairs is the history of the thought
processes behind the happening. This applies to the passing
of legislation as it does to any other human event.
4 The question of creating a GAAR (whether
targeted broadly at avoidance or narrowed to abuse) had been a common topic for
debate in the tax world—and Aaronson himself had been involved in
considering a GAAR in the field of indirect tax as long ago as 1996 when he was
head of Tax Law Review Committee. Although nothing came of
the proposals back in the late 1990s, the question of a statutory GAAR did not
go away, except in much of indirect tax where the European Court of Justice has
developed the abuse of law doctrine in matters of VAT.
5 Professor Freedman argues that, since the consideration
of a GAAR in the late 1990s, much had changed and not in the Revenue’s favour. The famous (in tax
circles) Ramsay doctrine, which had
threatened to cause tax law to address the real world results of entire
composite transactions, had been firmly
downgraded to a mere “approach”, and then became just another form
of statutory interpretation. As a result, tax
legislation had become even more complicated, particularly noting the
proliferation of Targeted Anti-Avoidance Rules (“TAARS”) designed
to plug gaps in specific pieces of legislation. This was the background to the establishment
of the Aaronson Committee to evaluate the question of introducing a GAAR. Finally,
to complete the story, the GAAR Study
somewhat melodramatically records that the very recommendation for any form of
General Anti-Avoidance Rule hung in the balance until along came the Court of
Appeal’s decision upholding the SHIPS 2 scheme in the Mayes Case, a scheme which united
Aaronson and his distinguished advisory panel in outrage, demonstrating the
pressing nature of the inadequacy of Britain approach to abusive tax avoidance.
6 But Professor Freedman presents too simple
a narrative. As long ago as the late 1980s, the House of Lords had already
turned Ramsay away from any potential
to develop into a doctrine of economic equivalence when Lord Templeman found himself in a minority of two in Craven v White, and the “statutory
construction” hypothesis was affirmed in the Inland Revenue’s
important victory in McGuckian. Lord Hoffmann muddied the
waters in MacNiven
(decided in 2000) by simultaneously affirming the “statutory
construction” approach and contradicting himself by asking the courts to categorise terms in tax statutes as either
“commercial” or “legal” in their meaning. This problem was resolved
in Barclays Mercantile Business Finance v
Mawson (“BMBF”) (decided in
2004), when the House of Lords
unanimously held that Lord Hoffmann’s words on “commercial”
and “legal” meanings had been misunderstood.
7 If MacNiven and BMBF
had been the only major avoidance cases, then there might have been a crisis
for HMRC. To this might have been added the Revenue’s defeat in Campbell, where the taxpayer achieved a loss by the simple expedient of gifting 10-year
securities in his own company to his wife—but in truth that
defeat in the relevant discounted securities legislation never gave the Revenue
a moment’s doubt that it would win the far more significant battle in Astall. Insofar as a casual
observer might have thought that the jurisprudence was swinging against HMRC
from the high point
of the 1980s, any downward trajectory was very much arrested by the trilogy of
2004 cases: Scottish Provident
Institution;
Carreras; and Arrowtown. These cases confirmed
that there was no judicial animus in favour of tax avoidance. There were defeats such as MacNiven and Campbell where the Revenue had pushed
the boundaries of statutory interpretation, and found that the words of the
statute were against them. A bare majority of the Privy Council may have held
in Peterson that the New Zealand GAAR
failed to counteract a scheme where borrowed money was used to artificially
inflate the amount spent on film production, but even this provided a
substantial weapon to the Revenue’s armoury:
the majority described how the New Zealand Revenue could have sought findings
of fact to demonstrate that certain expenditure was not on film production but
related to the recycling of loan moneys, an argument that pointed the way to
the landmark Revenue victory in Tower MCashback. In terms of work at the
coal face of Revenue anti-avoidance work, the defeat in BMBF was far less significant than the victory in Scottish Provident Institution which put
paid to “anti-Ramsay-devices”
by inserting a “commercially irrelevant contingency, creating an
acceptable risk that the scheme might not work as planned”. It meant that tax
planners could not claim that their schemes should not be viewed as a composite
whole because the outcome was not wholly certain, and that remote
contingencies inserted into schemes in order to tick statutory boxes would be
disregarded. The relevant discounted securities scheme that was thoroughly
routed in Astall may have been devised by a Big Four
accountancy firm, but cases such as Scottish
Provident Institution made defeating it straightforward. And in Prudential, another Big Four scheme, the
tax-efficient off market swaps scheme was calmly written off by the Revenue as
a straightforward case of Street v Mountford—what was said to be
“consideration for entering into a contract” was part of the
contractual quid pro quo however it
might be labeled—and a billion pound scheme vouched by many tax QCs was
practically laughed out of the Court of Appeal. Of course, given that
schemes inherently present factual scenarios that had not been considered,
there will be the luck of the draw as to whether the semantics of different
provisions will allow the Revenue to win the case—which it did not always
do. The repo legislation caused particular problems to HMRC with the defeats in
Bank of Ireland Britain Holdings (“BOIBH”), and then in First Nationwide, but these were more in
the nature of consolation goals scored by the tax avoidance industry than
evidence of a jurisprudential crisis for HMRC in the decade leading up to the GAAR Study.
8 Nor did the victory of the highly
artificial SHIPS 2 Scheme in Mayes
change the general flow of Revenue victories into such a crisis. The SHIPS 2 scheme was
exceedingly clever: the taxpayers invest a small amount of money by buying life
insurance policies and thanks to seven well-coordinated steps including the
borrowing of a large sum of money that never goes close to the taxpayers’
possession, a massive income loss is manufactured. Mayes may be the causus bellum put
forward by the GAAR Study as proving
the case for recommending the UK GAAR, but if on one view Mayes encapsulated what could go wrong
in the UK
tax system, it can also be said to be a rare occurrence. Pinsent
Masons claimed that it was “one of the only tax avoidance ‘schemes’
to succeed before the courts in recent times”. Pinsent
Masons, being the victorious solicitors in the case, may have cause to talk up
the scale of the victory but, as one of the principal firms for high-end
quality schemes, they hardly have cause to talk down the prospects of avoidance
schemes working. In any case, they would hardly make the claim unless it had a
significant basis in truth: Mayes was
a rare defeat for the Revenue. It cannot explain why a GAAR became necessary.
9 If there were no particular
jurisprudential crisis for HMRC in the measurement of income and expenditure,
then what? The reason for the idea of a GAAR re-entering the political agenda
was a decreased tolerance for the gap between reality and legal outcome. The
very nature of income does not admit of wholly accurate definition, meaning
that a set of rules will inevitably contain flaws that can be exploited, the
classic Haig-Simons definition of income being “consumption, plus
increase in net worth for any given period”. The problems of putting a
monetary value to the sum are well understood, not least by Simons himself who
said, “If one accepts our definition of income, one may be surprised that
it has ever been proposed seriously as a basis for taxation”. But as it would be
impossible in modern Britain (and almost the entirety of the modern world) to
wholly abandon the taxation of income, it is inevitable that governments will
look for means to either (a) define income so that it more precisely matched
the economic reality, or (b) deter tax planners and taxpayers from seeking to
identify and exploit mismatches. Many may hope that a GAAR will simplify the
tax system but at its heart the main object for a GAAR is to reduce the times
when tax statutes under-measure income or over-measure expenditure.
10 As the cry began to
go up that something had been done, Graham Aaronson, QC
stepped forward and brought the idea to the Treasury that the question of a
General Anti-Avoidance Rule should be considered in earnest to address the
question of whether the existing system does enough to prevent
“intolerable” avoidance. So 14 years after, as
head of the Tax Law Review Committee, he had promised that no General
Anti-Avoidance Rule would be passed against the wishes of tax practitioners, the Treasury commissioned
Graham Aaronson, QC to enquire again into whether there should be such a rule. What we shall see is
that, if Mayes was the causus bellum of Graham Aaronson’s GAAR Study, then war was declared on the
Mayes case and everything like it. Which
is to say, so-called egregious or abusive tax avoidance would be counteracted—but
it would be quite possible to find reasonable and responsible ways of economic
income being mismeasured by the Taxes Acts, even if
no reasonable or responsible legislature would leave such routes open once alerted to their existence. The Adam Smith Institute
deplored the motives behind the GAAR
Study—
“Mr. Aaronson soon decided that the crucial
question (for him) is whether current powers and legislation are effective
enough to prevent ‘the sort of tax-avoidance schemes which many citizens
and taxpayers regard as intolerable’. This is populism at its worst
. . .”
But the Institute was too busy deploring the idea of
the GAAR to notice the narrowness of the proposals, nor that the proposals in
fact protect much avoidance from being thought of as egregious.
The GAAR Study of 2011
11 The curious thing about the GAAR Study is that its central
pre-occupation is the protection of those who enter into tax planning from
HMRC, and not how best to narrow the gap between the statutory definition of
income and the economic reality.
12 The GAAR
Study, as we have said, railed against the SHIPS 2 Scheme. That Scheme was
intricate, clever, and did not pretend to be anything other than avoidance. But
any moral objection to the SHIPS 2 scheme working is no different from the
objection to any avoidance scheme, which is to do with objectionability
of what is achieved, something which must exist before we even consider whether
we wish to boo or hiss at the taxpayer who uses the scheme. As Milton Friedman put it—
“The effect has been to make the actual rates
imposed far lower than the nominal rates and, perhaps more important, to make
the incidence of the taxes capricious and unequal. People at the same economic level pay very different taxes depending on the
accident of the source of their income and the opportunities they have to
[avoid] tax.”
13 It really does not matter whether a
scheme works by one giant leap or seven well-choreographed pixie steps, or
whether the avoidance can be embedded in a commercial enterprise or not, the
reason why a taxpayer without a financial interest in the success of the scheme
will prefer a scheme to fail will be the same: the law should not create
an unjustifiable gap between the measurement of income and legal reality. It
will create justifiable albeit often controversial gaps when tax incentives are
created, but the heart and soul of tax avoidance is in the discovery and
exploitation of unjustifiable gaps. The success of SHIPS 2 in Mayes told us nothing that we did not
know from the taxpayer victories in MacNiven, BOIBH, Campbell
or BMBF v Mawson—facts
can be contrived to give a tax advantage that cannot be justified on any basis
other than the necessity to apply prior rules. The success of such schemes is
justified by “the rule of law, in the sense of the individual’s
safety against unlawful deprivation of rights and property, as a value that
overrides the fiscal interest in efficient taxation”, for certainly no one
could justify deliberately creating rules with the intention that those schemes
would achieve their goal.
14 The moralised
approach is crucial to the route taken in the GAAR Study’s recommendation, and also crucial to the
legislation that was introduced in the Finance Act 2013. The GAAR Study does not ask the question
“what would a legislature wish to fix in its tax code?”, but instead “when would we be angry with a taxpayer for
trying to take advantage of the faults in that code?” As we shall soon see,
the moralised approach is also crucial to what the UK
GAAR means for Jersey—which is to absolve Jersey from any future moral responsibility
for involvement in UK
tax avoidance.
GAAR Study recommendations
15 Setting aside procedural safeguards to
protect those who engage in high value tax planning, the basic legal structure
of the UK GAAR as proposed by Graham Aaronson, QC was this—
“[A]n abusive tax result is an advantageous tax
result . . . which would be achieved by an arrangement that is
neither reasonable tax planning . . . nor an arrangement without tax
intent . . .”
16 Disregarding the reference to
“arrangements without tax intent”, which was always irrelevant for
real-world purposes and would be wholly dropped from the final UK GAAR, the
definition can be unpacked as follows—
·
there must be an abnormal
arrangement,
·
giving rise to an
“advantageous tax result”,
·
which does not constitute
“reasonable tax planning”, in that it cannot “reasonably be
regarded as a reasonable exercise of choices of conduct afforded by the
provisions of the Acts”, and
·
the arrangement must be
contrived so as to achieve the advantageous tax result in that it has abnormal
features whose sole or main purpose was to achieve an advantageous tax result.
17 It is useful to state the component parts
of the UK GAAR as conceived by its creator: if an arrangement were found to be
abnormal, led to an advantageous tax result, and was found to have been created
solely to achieve that result, the question of whether it was reasonable tax
planning remained to be asked.
18 Whilst the question of anti-avoidance
legislation is for the legislature to better define what falls in and out of
the tax net, the focus of the GAAR Study is
whether “such a step might erode the attractiveness
of the UK’s
tax regime to business”. The central oddity of the
GAAR Study is that having taken care
to objectively identify “abnormal arrangements” and
“advantageous tax results”, these are in fact minor hurdles that
are easily cleared. The same applies with the treatment of taxpayers’
objectives for entering into he transactions. Usually
with Targeted Anti-Avoidance Rules, the major hurdle is proving that tax
avoidance was one of the main objects or purposes of the taxpayer, but in the GAAR Study
this hurdle is strangely lowered to what may “be reasonable to conclude”
as being the taxpayer’s purpose, as opposed to being
decided on the balance of probabilities. Everything makes way for the central
innovation of Aaronson’s proposals: the double reasonableness test. The
heart and soul of the Report was the “reasonably be regarded as
reasonable” safeguard to protect those achieving advantageous results by
way of abnormal arrangements from HMRC. There is little doubt on
reading the GAAR Study that, despite
occasionally hauling up the Mayes case
to serve as the tax avoidance equivalent of a pantomime villain, the true agent
of mischief addressed by the GAAR Study
was HMRC—the GAAR Study talked of “a palpable fear
of ‘mission creep’ after the GAAR reached the statute book”. It is this fear which led
to the proposal of many safeguards against HMRC, whilst not giving as much
as a thought as to how tax planners might try to “game” the system
by presenting specious commercial explanation, or withholding
documents relevant to motives by invoking legal privilege. Indeed, by (unusually for
tax appeals) placing the burden of proof on HMRC, the GAAR Study removed an
often useful lever to oblige the well-advised taxpayers to be forthcoming.
19 The approach taken in GAAR Study ultimately rests on the
central conviction that certainty in tax is of absolute importance to business.
The GAAR Study puts it thus—
“1.2 In broad terms the purpose of the study was to
consider whether the introduction of some type of general anti-avoidance rule
would be beneficial for the UK
tax system.
1.3 Beneficial does not mean simply providing another
weapon in the armoury to challenge unappealing
avoidance schemes. The issue is more complex, and a number of important factors
have to be taken into account to determine whether, looked at overall,
introducing a GAAR today would be a positive step.
1.4 Most critical among these factors is whether such a
step might erode the attractiveness of the UK’s tax regime to business. The
continuing turbulence in financial markets and the fragility of the UK
economy has kept this issue in the forefront of the Study Group’s
discussions.
1.5 I have concluded that introducing a broad spectrum
general anti-avoidance rule would not be beneficial for the UK tax system. This
would carry a real risk of undermining the ability of business and individuals
to carry out sensible and responsible tax planning.”
20 This conclusion, it is suggested here,
comes from a mixture of parochialism and special pleading. The approach is
parochial in that the tax experts behind the GAAR Study share the
common human fault of imagining that their speciality
is the centre of the world—the Adam Smith
Institute found the “plethora of lawyers” on Graham
Aaronson’s Committee “unfathomable”, but the position was
much worse: there was a plethora of tax lawyers. It can hardly be denied
that British business suffers all sorts of uncertainty at the hands of our
legal system: Lord Hope has asserted that anything in the common law of
contract might be changed retrospectively if found wanting; where a business owes a
duty of care in negligence can be re-written retrospectively if the courts
decide that the public policy factors have changed; British businesses have
no “double reasonableness” test to protect them in employment law; and health and safety law
is so vague that its own practitioners throw up numerous misconceptions to the
chagrin of the Health and Safety Executive. But the conclusion of the
GAAR Study was that business in Britain might bear
all of this legal indeterminacy, but what businesses absolutely require is
certainty as to when a plan for reducing the headline rate of corporation tax
will work. Should tax planners discover an opportunity to achieve “actual
rates . . . far lower than the nominal rates”, with this
opportunity “depending on the accident of the source of their income and
the opportunities they have to [avoid] tax”, then (in the world
according to GAAR Study) it is of fundamental
economic importance that the taxpayer should be certain as
to whether he will achieve that end. In the context of the present non-GAAR
approach of a purposive construction of tax statutes, and a realistic appraisal
of the facts engineered in schemes, Lord Walker in Tower MCashback dismissed fears of
uncertainty as something those who engage in avoidance planning bring on
themselves.
The GAAR Study implicitly rejects
this approach, save for those who test the limits of the UK GAAR
itself—after all, in its area of application the double-reasonableness
test of the UK GAAR offers no more precision than the double-reasonableness
test of classic British judicial review principles under Wednesbury. The UK GAAR does not
bring certainty through precision, but by deliberately vacating a significant
part of the battleground between the Revenue and tax planners, which is
henceforth declared to belong to responsible tax planning.
21 The result is that the UK GAAR is not a
General Anti-Avoidance Rule, but
rather a General Anti-Abuse Rule. This
is not because of any semantic argument that avoiding a statute is a contradiction
in terms,
but because the scope of the Report’s proposals was not tax avoidance in
general, but something much narrower, i.e.
abuse. The GAAR Study, far from
generally addressing tax avoidance, is very particular in its aim: “those
highly abusive contrived and artificial schemes which are widely regarded as
intolerable”. It is a moral judgment
against certain types of avoidance that is delivered by the GAAR—
“There was unanimous disapproval, indeed distaste,
for egregious tax avoidance schemes: schemes such as SHIPS 2 . . .
should be deterred or, if undeterred, defeated.”
And it is this moral judgment that
is adopted in the Finance Act 2013, ss 206–215
which, with a bit of tidying up, has implemented the proposals set out in the GAAR Study.
22 The Scheme of the UK GAAR as recommended
by Graham Aaronson, QC has remained, however, unchanged. The most important
feature of the UK GAAR, and the real hurdle to be cleared by HMRC, is found in
the concept of “abuse” and the double-reasonableness test of
whether there are “arrangements the entering into or carrying out of
which cannot reasonably be regarded as a reasonable course of action”.
Everything else is neither egregious nor abusive.
Significance for Jersey
23 The UK
GAAR, as we have said, will create a moralised
definition of the tax avoidance based on practical concerns for what is in the
best interests for the wider UK
economy. It is worth quoting Helen Lethaby of Freshfields where she summarises
the key value judgments underlying the UK GAAR—
“A GAAR should nevertheless deter and counteract
only ‘contrived and artificial schemes which are widely regarded as an
intolerable attack on the integrity of the UK’s tax regime’ and
leave untrammelled the ‘centre
ground of responsible tax planning’.”
24 The point for Jersey
is this. The UK
parliament will have made the decision that the vast majority of direct tax
planning should be policed by the GAAR, and this will include “abusive
arrangements which try to exploit particular provisions in a double tax
treaty”.
Some matters which deal with the division of the tax base in cross-border
transactions are recognized as being inappropriate for a UK GAAR, but essentially anything
which is by definition abusive tax avoidance will fail. Everything else may succeed
or fail—it may even fail by reason of a targeted anti-avoidance provision—but
it will not be abusive tax avoidance.
The UK
parliament will have created a statute which will make a moral judgment in
order to discover what tax planning is immoral, and such tax planning will be
doomed from the start. David Gauke in the House of
Commons noted that there would still be “tax avoidance” that the
Revenue would rather did not succeed, but this will not be of the
“abusive” variety. The yin and the yang of the
categorization recommended in the GAAR
Study, and accepted by Parliament when passing ss 206–215
of the Finance Act 2013, is that whatever is not “contrived and
artificial . . . an intolerable attack”, is in the “centre ground of responsible tax planning”.
25 The essence of the moral criticism of
Jersey banks, trust companies and the like for being involved in UK tax
avoidance schemes is the opinion that such entities ought not to hide behind
the assertion, true as it might be, that the success of failure of the scheme
is a matter for the legislature that passes the Taxes Acts and for the
tribunals and courts who interpret and apply that legislation. Doubtless, if
the Jersey institution had been told that the scheme does not work, then the
institution would know that it was being invited to assist a fraud, which of
course would be illegal under Jersey law. Indeed
there are such schemes which are more frauds on the taxpayers than on the
revenue, where sensible people who would not dream of purchasing the Tower of London or magic beans, somehow do the
fiscal equivalent. But our problem is not how financial institutions can spot
when they are being invited to have a walk-on role in what is (unknown to them)
a fraud, but how they should respond where the invitation is to assist a tax
scheme which is legal to try. In the world of legal tax avoidance, the truth is
that some schemes work and some schemes fail, and few whether on the Revenue
side or the taxpayer side will talk in terms of certainty of success or
failure. When SG Hambros Bank & Trust Co (Jersey) Ltd was asked to lend
money on a scheme involving the setting up of life insurance policies into
which a massive sum of money would be temporarily invested, with a massive tax
deduction coming out as if from thin air, those concerned may have thought that
it sounded too good to be true, but were surely entitled to say that it was a
matter for the British tax experts if it were worth a go. And, indeed, it was
worth a go: the scheme was SHIPS 2, the fiendishly clever scheme that the GAAR Study
went out of its way to condemn as immoral. But any moral criticism for the Jersey company’s involvement in
the scheme was that the scheme itself was immoral, and to assist the scheme was
to assist immorality.
26 Such an accusation could not be run
post-UK GAAR—it might be said that Code of Practice on Taxation for Banks
takes a tougher line, but now that statute has
created a moralized approach to what is reasonable and responsible, such lesser
forms of legal rules will surely be interpreted so as to fall into line. The
moral issues will have become tax-technical issues. If the scheme is egregious,
if it is abusive, if it is “intolerable attack” on the UK Revenue,
then anyone who in the future finds themselves in SG Hambros’ position in
respect of the SHIPS 2 scheme will know that those moral issues must have been
addressed by UK tax experts just as they would have addressed other tax-technical
issues. Such banks, trust companies and the like will not be participating in
the world-view specifically condemned in the GAAR Guidance—“Taxation is not to be treated as a game where
taxpayers can indulge in any ingenious scheme in order to eliminate or reduce
their tax liability”. Rather, the Jersey body
will be able to rest easy that issues of morality have been addressed. If, in
fact, the scheme is egregious, that will be taken care of in the manner
provided for by Parliament. Egregiousness is now just another way in which tax
planning will fail and—unless the Jersey institution has taken on the
role of tax planner, or somehow knows that a scheme is not designed to actually
work—providing a service towards implementing a tax scheme that turns out
not to work has never of itself been taken as a moral criticism.
27 We can see this in a recent tax avoidance
scheme, that of Vaccine Research. The scheme itself
involved the taxpayers paying £28m of their own money, of which £14m
eventually found into vaccine research, with the circulation of £86m in
bank loans. It was argued that the taxpayers, who had
formed a limited liability partnership, had incurred a first year loss of £193m.
The scheme was one which is apt in the UK press to be described as a Jersey
Scheme: the promoters were based in London SW1, the lawyers work out of Lincoln’s
Inn, the research company was in Britain, and taxpayers were of course British.
But the taxpayers formed their limited partnership in Jersey, and a Jersey company acted as company secretary. The scheme
failed in the First-tier Tribunal and is being optimistically appealed to the
Upper Tribunal. The scheme, as analysed by the GAAR
Advisory Committee’s Guidance, would also have failed under the UK GAAR
as being abusive tax avoidance. The reason it is abusive is precisely the same
as the reason the scheme failed for tax technical reasons: the taxpayers only
expended £14m on research because only £14m was consumed by the
research, and it was abusive to try to argue that money that never reached
research was spent on research. But no one would moralise
over a Jersey company failing to appreciate that the provisions of the Capital
Allowances Act 2001 did not allow the sort of fiscal alchemy claimed by the promoters—any
moral criticism of the Jersey company will be
based on the ethics of making such an attempt. And it is those ethics which the
GAAR addresses.
28 What is true for the Jersey companies who
participate is true for the Jersey
authorities. It is nothing to do with the States of Jersey if, as in Vaccine Research, British taxpayers form
an ordinary Jersey partnership and use it for
the purposes of egregious tax avoidance. But if it were in the future argued
that Jersey ought to prevent its regulated sector—its banks, trust
companies and the like—from participating, then Jersey can reply that
nothing in tax planning that is egregious can succeed. The UK parliament
has chosen to address tax avoidance not by taking steps against the tax
planners or against the taxpayers for participating in the schemes. In keeping
with the GAAR Study’s central
preoccupation, a distrust of HMRC, the conclusion was that creating a positive
downside for participants in schemes would present “an irresistible temptation
to HMRC to wield the GAAR as a weapon rather than to use it, as intended, as a
shield”. Given this approach by
the British Parliament, there is no logical reason for any other state or
territory to take such a step against its own institutions
for agreeing to take an ancillary role in implementation.
Lessons for Jersey’s
own anti-avoidance legislation
29 A question for Jersey is whether there
are any lessons from the UK GAAR that might be applied in respect of Jersey’s own approach to anti-avoidance. The answer
that we shall give here is, no. There are essentially two reasons. First, the
UK GAAR does not seek to address avoidance, but rather abuse. A legislature is
interested in the defining the tax base, anti-avoidance legislation should be a
tool for doing so. The UK GAAR’s chosen target is thus much narrower than
the Jersey GAAR. Secondly, despite the aspiration expressed in the GAAR Study
to simplify the UK
tax code, the published Guidance on the operation of the UK GAAR makes it clear
that it is easier to find schemes abusive when they are aimed at circumventing a
round or two of targeted anti-avoidance legislation. The UK GAAR appears to
presuppose complexity in the tax code. Thirdly, the bureaucracy of a GAAR
Advisory Panel and written guidance deemed essential in the United Kingdom would be wholly
inappropriate for a territory of about 100,000 people.
The Jersey
GAAR
30 Jersey’s General Anti-Avoidance
Rule, found in art 134A of the Income Tax (Jersey)
Law, is brief and to the point in comparison to the UK GAAR. It is worth
stating the principal provision in full—
“(1) If the Comptroller is of the opinion that the
main purpose, or one of the main purposes, of a transaction, or a combination
or series of transactions, is the avoidance, or reduction, of the liability of
any person to income tax, the Comptroller may, subject as hereinafter provided,
make such assessment or additional assessment on that person as the Comptroller
considers appropriate to counteract such avoidance or reduction of liability:
Provided that no assessment or additional assessment
shall be made under this Article if the person shows to the satisfaction of the
Comptroller either—
(a) that
the purpose of avoiding or reducing liability to income tax was not the main
purpose or one of the main purposes for which the transaction, or the
combination or series of transactions was effected; or
(b) that
the transaction was a bona fide commercial transaction, or that the combination
or series of transactions was a bona fide combination or series of transactions
and was not designed for the purpose of avoiding or
reducing liability to income tax.”
31 The Jersey GAAR is not encumbered by any
talk of “abnormal” arrangements, nor with explorations into the
reasonableness of the taxpayer entering into the planning.
32 The Jersey GAAR is instantly recognizable
to the present generation of tax practitioners as being based s 739 of the
Income and Corporation Taxes Act 1988 (“ICTA”)—the transfer
of assets overseas legislation. First, the Jersey GAAR is similar in broadly
addressing a transaction or a combination or series of transactions. Secondly, prima facie liability if there is a tax
avoidance motive for entering into the transaction or series of transaction. Thirdly,
as with s 739, there are two defences that the
taxpayer can raise: (i) a lack of tax avoidance
motive, and/or (ii) that the transaction (or transactions) were bona fide
commercial and not designed for the purpose of avoiding tax. The principal
difference is that the Jersey GAAR uses the broader language of
“avoidance or reduction”
taken from the transaction in securities legislation in ICTA,
s 703–709, powerful anti-avoidance legislation which was always kept
within well prescribed circumstances; in the Jersey GAAR, the
language of “tax reduction” (and not just avoidance) applies
generally.
33 Section 739 has appropriately been
described as “a potent piece of anti-avoidance legislation”, and the Jersey GAAR is at
least as potent. The Jersey GAAR follows the approach to anti-avoidance
provisions that the GAAR Study rejected when it raised the bar
for counteraction by introducing the double-reasonableness test.
Case-study—BMBF
34 HMRC’s GAAR Guidance has sought to demonstrate the strength and limits of the
UK GAAR with a series of case studies explaining which examples of tax planning
would fail the double-reasonable test, and thus be counteracted by the new
legislation. It will be useful to test the potential strength of the Jersey
GAAR against the tax planning in BMBF v Mawson—a scheme which succeeded as a matter of purposive statutory
construction, and is held up in the GAAR Guidance
as a quintessential example of responsible tax planning
notwithstanding this accurate description of the BMBF scheme from Helen Lethaby—
“No real finance was provided by the Barclays group
to the counterparty group; rather the Barclays group simply shared the benefit
generated by the tax savings made by the Barclays group with the counterparty
group.”
35 Essentially, contracts are drafted and
signed, book entries are made, ownership changes, but the owner’s ability
to use the property is unchanged. However, a large fiscal gain is accrued by
way of the capital gains legislation, which is supposed to provide an incentive
to investment.
But achieving a fiscal gain through such book entries was all, we are told, in
the spirit of the Taxes Acts.
36 The basic facts of BMBF were these. BGE owned a pipeline. It is common to raise
finance by way of sale-and-leaseback with banks. The bank is able to claim capital
allowances, which it can set against the profits that financial institutions
commonly made. The capital allowances were valuable to the bank, and allowed
for cheaper credit terms to be offered. What BGE did was to enter into a
sale-and-leaseback transaction with BMBF. BMBF borrowed from Barclays Bank the
money to buy the pipeline from BGE, and BGE (in a roundabout way) deposited the
sale price with Barclays as security for the rental payments on the pipeline
that it now leased from BMBF. The cashflows were such
that everything netted off, except that BMBF was able to claim capital
allowances of £91m, and mechanisms were included to share allow BGE to
share in the bounty. The taxpayers failed before the Special Commissioners and Mr Justice
Park in the High Court in
that the transactions lacked reality, for essentially the reasons given by
Helen Lethaby. The Court of Appeal and
House of Lords disagreed, as the only reality that mattered to the legislation
was the change of ownership, and so the scheme succeeded. The legislation did
not address any artificiality beyond the transfer of ownership in the course of
a business addressed by the statute.
37 So, despite the objections that can
readily be raised that a tax code ought not to allow a scheme such as BMBF to succeed, it did. BMBF is an example
of how purposive construction of taxing statutes can demonstrate how a fiscal
windfall can be achieved. Lethaby summarized it thus—
“Nevertheless the arrangements were found to be
acceptable by the House of Lords, largely it seems because, looked at from the
perspective of the Barclays company benefiting from the capital allowances, the
transactions were not out of the ordinary.”
38 The House of Lords stated—
“The finding of the special commissioners that the
transaction ‘had no commercial reality’ depends entirely upon an
examination of what happened to the purchase price after BMBF paid it to BGE.
But these matters do not affect the reality of the expenditure by BMBF and its
acquisition of the pipeline for the purposes of its finance leasing
trade.”
39 The official GAAR Guidance (as approved by the GAAR Advisory Committee)
enthusiastically agrees. The BMBF
scheme represents the “centre ground of
responsible tax planning” precisely because the result is achieved by
facts which addressed the core principle of the capital allowances legislation,
i.e. capital allowances for
expenditure on capital in the course of one’s trade. But the truth behind
almost every successful tax avoidance scheme is that Parliament did not
consider the possibility of the entirety of the transactions concerned—so
it is rather odd to analyse the abusiveness of tax
planning by looking at whether the facts relevant to answering the statutory
question naturally fit within the principles of the legislation.
40 This is, of course, the central
conceptual dilemma of tax avoidance. Lord Hoffmann was right to say—
“There is only one way to know the intention of
Parliament and that is to read the statute. So avoidance of tax assumes that
you are not paying a tax which, on a fair reading of the statute, you ought to
have paid. But why in that case are you not liable to pay it? How can the
courts give the statute a construction which means that people do not pay the
tax which the statute shows that Parliament intended them to pay?”
41 It thwarts the purpose of an
anti-avoidance rule if we tend to collapse the key test for the application of
the rule to the same sort of analysis which decides whether
or not the scheme works according to the substantive taxing provisions. We can
see the UK GAAR’s tendency to reproduce the results of ordinary non-GAAR
adjudication if we consider HMRC’s GAAR
Guidance. Frequently the reason for a scheme being held to be egregious is
precisely the same reason for the scheme failing, e.g. Vaccine Research—as
explained earlier, the scheme failed because only £14m and not £193m
was spent on research, so only £14m could be deducted; and it was
egregious to claim to have made a loss of £193m for the same reason.
42 It should be noted that a version of the BMBF scheme—The Queen v Canadian Trustco Mortgage Co—was
held by the Canadian Supreme Court not to fall within that country’s GAAR. The Canadian GAAR has
essentially three hurdles—
(a) There needs
to be a tax benefit—this is equivalent to the Jersey GAAR requirement
that tax should be avoided or reduced.
(b) The
arrangements will fall outside the GAAR is they were “arranged primarily
for bona fide purposes other than to obtain the tax benefit”—which
means, as with the Jersey GAAR, that someone lacking a tax avoidance as one of
the main purposes, or entering into bona fide commercial transactions will fall
outside the GAAR. In fact, the Canadian GAAR is slightly more generous to
taxpayers—if any non-tax reason is the primary purpose for the
transactions, then the GAAR will not apply.
(c) Finally,
the Canadian GAAR “does not apply to a transaction where it may
reasonably be considered that the transaction would not result directly or
indirectly in a misuse of the provisions of this Act . . .”
This provision, minus the second use of the word “reasonable”, is
broadly equivalent to the test for abuse in the UK GAAR—and it is, of
course, wholly without an equivalent in the Jersey GAAR.
43 The point from the Jersey GAAR
perspective is that in Canadian Trustco the Canadian Revenue succeeded in demonstrating
points “a” and “b” applied. Were the Comptroller of
Taxes to succeed on those points when applying art 134A of the 1961 Law, then
the counteraction would be successful. The Canadian Revenue failed to show
“misuse” under point “c”—but the Comptroller of
Taxes in Jersey would not need to do so.
44 This is not to say that if BMBF were fought in Jersey
tomorrow that the scheme would fail. It would depend on the finding of fact by
the first instance tribunal as to purpose. The leading case on commercial
purpose is that of Brebner v IRC, where somewhat convoluted
transactions were held by the Special Commissioners to have had such a purpose.
That finding was upheld by the House of Lords as within the range of reasonable
decisions—but it is also clear that they would have upheld the opposite
finding had the first instance tribunal ruled in favour
of the Revenue.
This is the type of uncertainty that the GAAR
Study found intolerable—although, of course, the question of what is
egregious will often depend on whether the tribunal members’ own
experience leads them to believe that a particular scheme has aspects that are
out of the ordinary. There may be many cases where there is no doubt about
avoidance motive, but the reasonableness of the tax planning might be a live
issue under the UK GAAR. UK GAAR or Jersey GAAR,
there will always be uncertainty at the point of
application. The point is rather that the Jersey GAAR is a broad spectrum
anti-avoidance rule—it may not be targeted so as to guarantee victory
against all schemes, but (unlike the UK GAAR) it is not targeted so as to
guarantee a Revenue defeat on many avoidance schemes.
45 The Jersey GAAR means that any avoidance
schemes in Jersey face uncertainty—and it does so because it has the
potential to close the gap between what the Income Tax (Jersey) Law achieves on
its ordinary construction and the accurate measurement of income and
expenditure. But even though it cannot achieve that goal with total certainty,
such uncertainty has distinct advantages from the perspective of the Revenue
authority. It is also what Lord Walker said in Tower MCashback is an occupational hazard
for those who enter into clever tax planning.
The complicating tendency of the UK GAAR
46 The second reason for Jersey
having little to learn from the UK GAAR is the tendency of the new British
legislation to promote complexity and cost.
47 First, there are flaws in the stated aspiration of the GAAR Study that the UK GAAR should lead
to a simplification in tax legislation as complex provisions designed to
prevent avoidance prove to be unnecessary. One flaw has already been labored in
this article—the UK GAAR does not purport to tackle avoidance in general,
so for non-egregious avoidance, more traditional statutory methods will be
necessary. Furthermore, the idea that the UK GAAR will promote simplicity in
substantive taxing legislation is misguided: the UK GAAR is weakest in the face
of simple legislation. If an avoidance scheme is put together so as to take advantage of simple
legislation (such as in BMBF) then
such a scheme will most likely be held to be in the central ground of
responsible tax planning. By contrast, if the same
legislation has been complicated by one or two attempts by the Revenue to
counter such schemes, then it is likely that further attempts to circumvent the
legislation will be found to be unreasonable. Such a finding will derive not
just from the legislature having made clear the economic substance that the
provision seeks to address, but also because, as the legislation becomes more
complicated, so it will typically require more obviously artificial and
contrived transactions to make schemes work. The UK GAAR will find its happiest
hunting grounds where legislation is prescriptive.
48 Secondly, there is the bureaucracy
created for the UK GAAR. If Jersey were to go
down the double-reasonableness route, then the question would arise as to
whether to bring into place similar guidance and a similar committee. It is
common for Jersey statutes to enact the same general principles as their UK
equivalents but to miss out the explanatory detail. An example is the
Matrimonial Causes (Jersey) Law 1949—it follows the UK’s Matrimonial Causes Act
1973 in making “fairness in all the circumstances” the guiding
principle for ordering ancillary relief, but does not reproduce the long list
of factors to be taken into account found in s 25(2) of the 1973 Act. This
has not led to any difference in approach. But such an approach
would be harder to take with the United Kingdom’s GAAR Guidance and any jurisprudence that
were to emerge on the application of the GAAR. Jersey and the United Kingdom’s tax legislation is too
different in too many places for Jersey to do
anything other than to find its way in many areas of tax. If the purpose of the
UK GAAR is to deliver increased certainty to those who implement complex tax
planning, and if that purpose requires GAAR
Guidance and a GAAR Advisory Panel, then the appropriateness of the United Kingdom’s
approach to a small jurisdiction must be very much doubted.
Conclusion
49 What this article has sought to show is
that, from the perspective of the frequent criticisms of the role of Jersey
companies in UK
tax avoidance schemes, that the new UK GAAR will assist greatly. Up to now, it
has been very easy for those in the United Kingdom to make a moral criticism of
Jersey (and other offshore jurisdictions) for being involved in what were
essentially British schemes, as if those outside the United Kingdom should
refuse on moral grounds to work with those in Britain to do something that was
perfectly legal in Britain. By enacting a level of “egregiousness”
above which schemes must fail, Jersey
companies are released from such criticism. The morality of the scheme, as
defined in the UK GAAR, is now very much a matter for the expert UK tax planners, and those outside Britain
can be involved in transactions in the secure knowledge that the egregiousness
will have been addressed. This is not to say that UK
tax planners will always come to the right conclusion as to whether the UK GAAR
will apply or not—but from an outsider’s perspective this is no
different from any other issue of UK tax law. That has always been
the approach for Jersey banks, trust companies
and the like, it is just now that such an approach cannot be said to be amoral,
for the appropriate level of morality is now wrapped up in the law.
50 The second conclusion in this article is
that the Jersey GAAR is simpler and broader than the UK GAAR. It will apply to
a larger number of schemes, and have a broader deterrent effect against those
who might be tempted to adapt UK
schemes to Jersey tax law. The Jersey GAAR
comes without a bloated bureaucracy of lengthy GAAR Guidance and a GAAR Advisory Panel before a case comes
anywhere near the tax tribunal. It is in short, much more appropriate to Jersey, and it is difficult to see what in the UK GAAR
ought to be imported. Michael Meacher MP, proposing
the introduction of a GAAR into the United
Kingdom back in 2009, commented that such legislation
existed in Jersey and seemed “to be working
perfectly well”—a comparison with
the new UK GAAR shows it to be very much at the strong-end of such provisions.
Dennis Dixon is a Legal Adviser at the Law Officers’
Department, Jersey, and previously worked as a
lawyer for HMRC for most of the period 1997–2012, including eight years
in anti-avoidance litigation. All views expressed are his own.